Friday, December 28, 2012

Piddleville

A site for movie lovers, with as far as I have seen a sensibility like my own. I enjoy just poking around it, reading his reactions to old movies I love. My Man Godfrey for one. Piddleville.

Wednesday, November 14, 2012

Stravinsky Day

Over at Gene Callahan's. It spreads over several posts. Very clever.
UPDATE: Gene's an economist much concerned with theories of value. This seems appropriate.

Odd Even Rationing and Queue Effects

In a thread over at Bob Murphy's I made the case that segregating drivers into Odd and Even days for buying gas will usually just make things worse. I gave several abstract reasons why. Later Bob collected these and his own contributions into a coherent statement, since revised, and he plans another post to lay out the arguments more fully. (Here) In support I am going to present a simple numerical example to illustrate what I think is the main effect: unbalancing queues.

Left to themselves drivers will join lines when they are shorter and avoid them when they are longer. This smoothes out the queue lengths. Odd/Even prevents drivers from doing this. How?
Imagine Bob has an odd plate and is driving on an even day. He sees a shortish line but cannot join it.
Or next day Bob is wondering if he has enough gas. He'd like to wait and see, but the rationing makes waiting risky: he might not be able to wait two days. He'll join the line even if it is long.
Or perhaps there are just more odd-plated drivers where Bob lives, so the lines are longer on odd days.

Odd/Even rationing unbalances queues.

Consider then two queues.
Each driver in the queue takes one time period to get and pay for gas.
This isn't realistic, as some buy more gas, and some piddle around with cash, but it will do as a first approximation.
And let's further assume that new cars arrive at one per time unit at the end of the queue.
This is more subtle.
Drivers are reluctant to queue when the line gets long, and eager to queue when it shortens. So we will generally reach a period of approximate equilibrium where the line reaches a steady length. Not exact but close enough for government work. I'll discuss the other cases below in case this assumption worries you.

We can think of just the people in the queues at a given moment.
So lets put 3 people in queue Even and 5 people in queue Odd

Even: a b c
Odd : P Q R S T

(This is 5-3 split is perfectly fair on my part: I am examining the effects of unbalancing the queues, and a difference of 2 is the smallest relevant difference.  S's arrival would lengthen one queue no matter what but T was compelled to join the longer queue when he arrived.  Add another Odd driver and it gets even worse. So this example shows the smallest effect of forced unbalancing.)

What's the total amount of waiting and filling for these folks?
In Even it is 1 for a, then 2 for b (he waits for a then spends his time) and 3 for c (who starts when b is done). Total 6.
And in queue Odd it is 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5. Total 15.
Grand total 21.

What if T could move into queue Even? Then we get 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 for each queue.
Grand total 20.

So the inability to smooth out queues has made things worse.

This holds even if the queues keep getting longer until say 9 pm or if some people randomly take longer than others.

Now what happens if new people don't arrive as fast as the queue empties? This will happen late at night for example. Then we get shorter or empty queues and the costs are more obvious. For example after 3 periods queue Even is empty and in queue Odd person T is still waiting when he could have found an empty pump. Segregation has cost T and benefitted no-one.

And what happens when people arrive faster at the tail end? Then the queues keep getting longer. Since our population is finite we have to eventually reach the steady state or the shrinking queue case. We already looked at those.

And what if not everyone uses the same amount of time at the pump? Then it gets a bit trickier and all results become probabilistic. But the main effect remains.
Let people use between 1 and 4 units of time once they pull up to the pump.
Then we get queues that look like this, replacing names with pump times:

Odd: 1 3 3 2 1 4 2 1 4

To calculate the time spent pumping and filling start at tail-end Charley.
He waits for everyone ahead. Here that is 1 + 3 + 3 + 2 + 1 + 4 + 2 + 1.
Then he pumps for 4. So his elapsed time is the sum of everyone's pump time up to and including himself. This is true of driver n, his time is the sum of all times of drivers 1 through n.

If you play around you'll find you want (more or less) queues with even pump times.
So segregation by pump time can help. Think of express lanes at the supermarket: lots of fast shoppers in lane Odd and a few with big baskets in lane Even. Imagine 6 odds at a minute each and three evens at 4 minutes each.
Then we get this:

Odd: 1 1 1 1 1 1
Even : 4 4 4

The totals are 21 and 24, which is pretty closely balanced.
In this example odd/even segregation benefits these drivers. But this example is pretty special.  Any arbitrary form segregation can in fact by dumb luck help achieve pump time segregation. Odd/even or bald/hirsute can conceivably give us pump time segregation. Giving blue-eyed drivers priority can also, by blind luck, more the faster drivers to the front of the line. But the chances are remote. In the real world, odd/even is far more likely to make things worse.

It's common sense really, disguised by the time shifting. You ever see the line-up at the women's during intermission?

Monday, November 12, 2012

Paging Bob Murphy

A woman offered us raffle tickets, 3 for $5.
"How much for just one?"
"Oh, we only sell them in bunches of 3."
There's a Keynesian fable in there somewhere.

Thursday, November 8, 2012

Writing Landsburg

In one of the skirmishes in The Great Debt War Bob Murphy and I tussled over the proper understanding of Steve Landsburg's arguments. I suggested asking Steve to clarify, and Bob graciously agreed on sending a joint note. Here it is:
Steve

I am writing this jointly with Bob Murphy.

The discussion of debt-as-burden on FreeAdvice has become so complicated that we cannot even agree on what *your* position is. I am hoping you will be willing to clear this up. Here then is my ( Ken B) understanding:

Krugman’s argument is that borrowing rather than taxing imposes no extra burden on unborn Americans in toto, because both are transfers between living persons, and that any burdens are caused not by debt per se but by transfer and incentive effects. (Bob would describe Krugman's position a bit differently, but this is Ken's understanding of it.)  Krugman’s argument relies on the constraint that internally held debt represents a flow of assets is within a given pool, and so the pool is not directly diminished by the debt. The debtor and lender are part of the same closed system.

Steve endorses but extends this argument. Steve observes that Krugman is missing a point which strengthens and extends his claim: if the foreigner owns a bond because he paid for it we include the payment in the pool's assets the constraint is re-established. (One can also see the initially foreign held cash as a claim against future earnings already, so all we are seeing is an exchange, cash for cash flow, not a new burden.)

Steve’s argument relies on the same constraint as Krugman’s, that debt is just exchange amongst living people, not an extraction from the future. This is clear if you take a case where foreign interactions are *impossible*, so that SL's argument reduces to PK's.

Bob thinks there's nothing wrong with your own position, but he just thinks it is weird to say "Steve is strengthening Krugman's point" when, in Bob's mind, you are actually advancing a totally different argument. In contrast, I think you are amplifying Krugman's point, by showing that Krugman doesn't even need to focus on whether future Americans "owe it to themselves."

We'd appreciate any clarification, and also let us know whether you want your response to remain private.
Steve kindly replied and his answer is below, with permission:
Ken and Bob:

I was about to say that your statement of my position is accurate,
succinct, and beautifully expressed.

But I think I'd rather say that your statement of my *point* is accurate, succinct, and beautifully expressed, because a "position" is something controversial, whereas this point is, I think, not controversial at all.  (It's often disputed, but that's not the same thing as controversial ---- "disputed" means some people don't understand it, whereas "controversial" means that even people who understand it sometimes disagree.  I do not think this point is controversial.)

As to whether this is an *extension and strengthening* of Krugman's point or an *additional point*, that, I think might be controversial and could be argued either way.

I should add that when I say this point is not controversial, I must admit to not being up to date on Bob's blog, and perhaps he has already proven me wrong.  He clearly understands the point completely; if he disagrees with it, then I guess it's controversial after all.

I'd like to quote your email on my blog next week (maybe not till
late in the week cause I'm quite swamped for the next few days).
Is that okay?
 I hope to see Steve's followup.

Thanks to both Bob for his co-operation and Steve for his kind words.

Musical Anatomy

Of In Re Don Giovanni. Odd but interesting, and rapturous music.

Of Philip Glass. Rather less respectful!

Of Mission Impossible. I just thought it was cool; who knew?



Bonus: A mass by Virgil Thomson. No anatomy, just music.

Monday, November 5, 2012

The Great FeeAdvice Debt War of 2012

A war on public debt and Paul Krugman has been raging over at FreeAdvice. On the one side are Krugman's defenders, principally me and Gene Callahan, versus his critics, principally Bob Murphy, Nick Rowe and Major_Freedom. The debate has spread over many threads, and even some other blogs, and become so diffuse and shambling that I want to summarize my case for Krugman here.

Krugman argues that internally held debt cannot in any direct way impoverish America as a whole. Internal borrowing rather than taxing imposes no extra burden on any future America in toto, because both are transfers between then living Americans. Internally held debt represents a flow of assets is within a given pool, and so the pool is not directly diminished by the debt. Krugman gives a good analogy: Imagine a "Santorum tax" that just transfers funds between Americans. Leaving an internally held debt is just like a Santorum tax.

I think Krugman's argument is sound, convincing, and correct. But Bob Murphy and Nick Rowe insist, reasonably enough, that the claim be tested against some models to see if they can disprove it. Bob presents his model, and claimed counter-example, here. The rest of the discussion takes place within the context of this model.

At first blush it looks like Bob has made a point. We do indeed see people who eat fewer apples. But in fact this is not a counter example at all. I'll come back to why but we must first translate Krugman's claim into this model. Krugman talks about future states of America.

The natural and correct interpretation of Krugman here is that a state of the whole country at any moment corresponds to a row in the table, and a period of time corresponds to a contiguous block of rows. (We know this is what he means because he tells us so with the Santorum tax). Krugman's assertion is that at no point in time and for no period of time is a future America impoverished. This is plainly true in the model: each row (point in time) has 200 apples. The period claim follows from the point in time claim. If that's what a future state really is, then Krugman's claim holds in this model.

So the question reduces to: is this the appropriate definition of future state? Bob's example assumes not. Rather than level sections, Bob presents diagonal sections. He includes for example Young Frank, Old Frank, Young George, Old George but not Young Hank or Old Eddy, slicing diagonally through the table. In any of his slices there is always one person from the first level and one from the last level omitted. And this is the problem. At no point in time and for no period of time are the people and assets of a diagonal section co-extensive with the population and assets of the Island. In the real world a slice like this might include all the people whose names end in vowels who were born before 2012 and all those who names do not end in vowels who were born after 1970. That diagonal section never, not for a moment, not for a period, is all and only the population of the country. A diagonal section is not a state of the country. Bob's diagonal sections may be interesting -- I will return to this point -- but they do not correspond to a future state of the country. Since they do not refer to what Krugman is talking about -- future states -- they cannot be counterexamples to Krugman's claim.

So Bob's construction is not a counterexample after all. But don't Bob diagonal sections show something? After all he seems to show a loan impoverishing 65 generations. Doesn't that prove something? No, not about the aggregate consequences of debt anyway.

First Bob's example does not show one loan affecting 65 generations. He shows 65 consecutive loans affecting 65 consecutive generations. In each case the whole daisy chain would be ended unless each generation takes from the next while both are alive. Gene Callahan put this well: I can eat my son's desert, and when I am dead he can eat his own son's desert, but that doesn't mean I ate my grandson's desert. I explicate this point in detail in comments on that thread. Borrowing from Young Hank does not burden the future, it burdens Hank.

Do Bob's diagonal sections correspond to anything meaningful? Perhaps they do, but not for the purpose of looking at the aggregate effect of debt or transfers. I illustrate this with an example where imposing a debt on a diagonal section seems to enrich it. This is pretty odd if you want to argue the section corresponds to something meaningful, which is burdened by the infliction of a debt. But a diagonal section is really just an incomplete set of accounts. There is no mystery why you can make an incomplete set of accounts seem unbalanced in odd ways.

So Krugman is right, in detail, and Rowe and Murphy have merely exhibited a combinatorial artifact, which they misinterpret.

Debt enriches the future?

My latest salvo in the ongoing war at Free Advice.
Here it is. I hope the formatting is decent:
Can a debt *enrich* the future? By Bob's criteria it can.
Let's look at the example of Apple Atol, just a few miles from Apple Island where their policies differ.
In period 1 govt borrows 1  at 100% from young A for old Z.

In period 2 govt borrows 2  at 100% from young B and pays off the loan to old A.
In period 3 govt borrows 4  at 100% from young C and pays off the loan to old B.
In period 4 govt borrows 8  at 100% from young D and pays off the loan to old C.

In period 5 govt borrows 16 at 100% from young E and pays off the loan to old D.
At this point the Atol switches policies to get a steady state. There are many ways to do this.
Govt can tax the youngster 8 and borrow from the youngster 8 at 100%, or borrow from the youngster 16 at 0%.
Let's use the latter.
In period 6 govt borrows 16  at 0% from young F and pays off the loan to old E.

In period 7 govt borrows 16  at 0% from young G and pays off the loan to old F.

In period 8 govt borrows 16  at 0% from young H and pays off the loan to old G.
etc
I lack Bob's mad table skills but let me show the resulting data
oq 100 yz 100
oz 101 ya 99
oa 102 yb 98
ob 104 yc 96
oc 108 yd 92
od 116 ye 84
oe 116 yf 84
of 116 yg 84
oh 116 yi 84

Now let's do Bob's diagonal sums.
Everyone ends up with at least 200, and some end up with more than 200. C gets 204.
The future, by Bob's critria, has been enriched.
A few other things to note. This example runs on pure debt, not defaults and not taxes, but there are several ways to produce such examples.
Old Z is better off too, no-one is harmed.
By the Krugmanite criteria, the Atol is not enriched.

For style points, the govt can just destroy the apple it borrows from ya.
Then the chart changes to "oz 100 ya 99"
That leaves Z out of the windfall, but the Bob-defined enrichment still works with no-one losing out *even with an apple destroyed*.
By the Krugmanite criteria the style points apple destruction impoverishes the present, without aiding the future. Broken windows anyone?

I suggest this example shows Bob's crtiteria are wonky, and that the limits of integration are inappropriate.

Wednesday, June 13, 2012

Casting stones at Bob Murphy's favorite story

In our last episode, Bob Murphy was, as is his wont, playing WWJD with some of his commenters. They were arguing, over several threads, that Jesus would kill homosexuals. They argued from Jesus's endorsement, both implicit and explicit, of traditional Jewish law.

Murphy, rather emotionally, rebutted them with a familiar story about Jesus.
There are two problems with Bob's response: the story isn't about gays, and it never happened.

The story is, of course, the woman taken in adultery from John 8. Bob bases his argument on Jesus's dictum "let him who is without sin cast the first stone." This is a story about the law on adultery not homosexuality. Perhaps this dictum would apply to the law on homosexuality too, but then it would presumably apply rather more broadly than Murphy might like. Murder? Rape? Would Jesus tell murderers and thieves to go and sin no more? Is there any criteria we can use to decide?  This is a common problem when playing WWJD.

But there is a more serious problem with Bob's pericope (to use some jargon). It never happened. It's a late invention, inserted into John centuries after John was redacted.  It does not occur in <i>any</i> early manuscripts of John.  It does not occur in the <i>best</i> manuscripts.  It does not occur in early discussions of John.  It is not cited in early discussions of adultery. It is not mentioned by any early church writers.  Its language does not match John. It breaks the natural flow of the surrounding text.  It is called late by medieval writers.  It presents an implausible picture of how Jewish law was carried out. It presents an implausible view of the Pharisees.  It simply does not belong in John. It's a late invention.

That's not just my opinion, it's the scholarly concensus. Even my Crossway Bible has a note about the passage. Perhaps Bob should read his Bible ...

Here for example is Bruce Metzger on the passage:
The evidence for the non-Johannine origin of the pericope of the adulteress is overwhelming. It is absent from such early and diverse manuscripts as Papyrus66.75 Aleph B L N T W X Y D Q Y 0141 0211 22 33 124 157 209 788 828 1230 1241 1242 1253 2193 al. Codices A and C are defective in this part of John, but it is highly probable that neither contained the pericope, for careful measurement discloses that there would not have been space enough on the missing leaves to include the section along with the rest of the text. In the East the passage is absent from the oldest form of the Syriac version (syrc.s. and the best manuscripts of syrp), as well as from the Sahidic and the sub-Achmimic versions and the older Bohairic manuscripts. Some Armenian manuscripts and the old Georgian version omit it. In the West the passage is absent from the Gothic version and from several Old Latin manuscripts (ita.l*.q). No Greek Church Father prior to Euthymius Zigabenus (twelfth century) comments on the passage, and Euthymius declares that the accurate copies of the Gospels do not contain it.
When one adds to this impressive and diversified list of external evidence the consideration that the style and vocabulary of the pericope differ noticeably from the rest of the Fourth Gospel (see any critical commentary), and that it interrupts the sequence of 7.52 and 8.12 ff., the case against its being of Johannine authorship appears to be conclusive.
This tale is central to Murphy's idea of a kinder, gentler Jesus, and that is a major theme on his blog. Bob gets testy when I point out the problems, but he has never responded.

Aliens Cause Global Warming

A classic by the late Michael Crichton.

Tuesday, June 12, 2012